Copyright holder: Tyndale University, 3377 Bayview Ave., Toronto, Ontario, Canada M2M 3S4 Att.: Library Director, J. William Horsey Library Copyright: This Work has been made available by the authority of the copyright owner solely for the purpose of private study and research and may not be copied or reproduced except as permitted by the copyright laws of Canada without the written authority from the copyright owner. Copyright license: Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License Citation: Gould, Paul M. and Richard Brian Davis. “Modified Theistic Activism,” in Beyond the Control of God? Six Views on the Problem of God and Abstract Objects, edited by Paul M. Gould, pages 51-79. New York: Bloomsbury Press, 2014. ***** Begin Content ****** TYNDALE UNIVERSITY 3377 Bayview Avenue Toronto, ON M2M 3S4 TEL: 416.226.6620 www.tyndale.ca Note: This Work has been made available by the authority of the copyright owner solely for the purpose of private study and research and may not be copied or reproduced except as permitted by the copyright laws of Canada without the written authority from the copyright owner. Gould, Paul M. and Richard Brian Davis. “Modified Theistic Activism,” in Beyond the Control of God? Six Views on the Problem of God and Abstract Objects, edited by Paul M. Gould, pages 51-79. New York: Bloomsbury Press, 2014. [ Citation Page ] Bloomsbury Studies in Philosophy of Religion Series Editor: Stewart Goetz Editorial Board: Thomas Flint, Robert Koons, Alexander Pruss, Charles Taliaferro, Roger Trigg, David Widerker, Mark Wynn Titles in the Series Freedom, Teleology, and Evil by Stewart Goetz Image in Mind: Theism, Naturalism, and the Imagination by Charles Taliaferro and Jil Evans Actuality, Possibility, and Worlds by Alexander Robert Pruss God’s Final Victory: A Comparative Philosophical Case for Universalism by John Kronen and Eric Reitan The Rainbow of Experiences, Critical Trust, and God by Kai-man Kwan Thinking Through Feeling: God, Emotion and Passibility by Anastasia Philippa Scrutton Philosophy and the Christian Worldview: Analysis, Assessment and Development edited by David Werther and Mark D. Linville Goodness, God and Evil by David E. Alexander Well-Being and Theism: Linking Ethics to God by William A. Lauinger Free Will in Philosophical Theology by Kevin Timpe The Moral Argument (forthcoming) by Paul Copan and Mark D. Linville [ Series Listing Page ] Beyond the Control of God? Six Views on the Problem of God and Abstract Objects Edited by Paul M. Gould B L O O M S B U RY NEW YORK • LONDON • NEW DELHI • SYDNEY [ Title Page ] [ Chapter ] 2 Modified Theistic Activism Paul M. Gould and Richard Brian Davis It is not easy to give an illuminating definition of an abstract object. According to Morris and Menzel, an abstract object is (at the very least) an object “so firmly rooted in reality that [it] could not possibly have failed to exist” (1986, 161).1 This characteri- zation is not sufficient of course, since if classical theism is true, God is a necessary being; it is not possible for Him not to exist. And no one thinks God is an abstract object. Philosophers working in this area have therefore tended to proceed by giving examples. Abstract objects are said to be impersonal entities: such things as properties, relations, propositions, numbers, sets, and the like. Plantinga expresses the view of many here: An abstract object, he says, is “an object that (like God) is immaterial, but (unlike God) is essentially incapable of life, activity, or causal relationships” (1985, 88)? Of course if you are wondering what nontrivial relationship holds between God and abstracta, this is not the most helpful way to put things. For it implies right up front that God cannot be causally related to abstracta, in which case it is difficult to see how there could be anything but a trivial two-way relation of logical dependence between them. This is just to say that in every world in which God exists (that is, in every world), abstract objects also exist. But there is no deeper (asymmetrical) sense in which abstract objects depend for their existence on God. There are powerful reasons for thinking this sort of “platonistic theism” is incompatible with classical theism, though we will not take the time to survey them here.3 Conceptualism is the attempt to identify abstracta with divine ideas or concepts, which by the very nature of the case would depend on God as thoughts on a thinker— that is, causally and asymmetrically. In this respect, so-called theistic activism is simply a strong form of conceptualism: One holding that “all properties and relations are God’s concepts ... the contents of a divine intellective activity” (Morris and Menzel 1986, 166, emphasis added). However, a proper theistic activist also maintains that All necessarily existent propositions ... can be thought of as “built up” out of properties. Thus, in the way in which we characterize properties as God’s concepts, we can characterize propositions as God’s thoughts... . And taking numbers to be a variety of property, we thus have all necessarily existent abstract [ Page 51 ] [ Page ] 52 reality, from necessary mathematical objects to haecceities, to nonmathematical universals, to propositions, deriving existence from God. (ibid.) So the suggestion is that divine concepts are ontologically basic; everything else in the platonic horde is a derivative entity: a complex construction on God’s mental concepts. In what follows, we shall argue two things. First, it is plausible to think that conceptualism holds with respect to propositions; in any event, it does a much better job than its closest competitors (platonism and nominalism) in accounting for the truthbearing nature of propositions. Secondly, it is wholly implausible (so we say) to take the added step and equate properties and relations with divine concepts. Thus, a modified theistic activism (MTA) emerges as the most natural and defensible way for a theist to think about Gods relation to abstract objects. Recipe for a proposition Let us begin with propositions. What are they? Here we can do no better than to begin with Lord Russell's insight: “The fundamental characteristic which distinguishes propositions (whatever they may be) from objects of acquaintance is their truth or falsehood” (1984, 108). Propositions are truthbearers. We know this (or can at least stipulate it) pretheoretically. So consider the proposition (1) Quine is wise. The question arises: How is it that (1) manages to be true? Naturally, the truth-condi- tions for this proposition must obtain: Quine himself must exist and have the property of being wise. But surely there are conditions to be met on the side of the proposition as well—truthbearer conditions, as we might call them. Surely (1), to have a truth value at all, whether true or false, has to be a claim or an assertion of some kind. It must represent reality as being a certain way. Thus Alvin Plantinga: Propositions are claims, or assertions; they attribute or predicate properties to or of objects; they represent reality or some part of it as having a certain character. A proposition is the sort of thing according to which things are or stand a certain way. (1987, 190) Similarly G. E. Moore: propositions, in the sense in which I have been using the term, are obviously a sort of thing which can properly be said to be true or false... . Every proposition is, as we constantly say, a proposition about something or other. Some propositions may be about several different things; but all of them are about at least one thing. (1953, 62, 68, emphasis added) In short, propositions (again, whatever they are) are intentional objects; they are of or about things. And this is an essential property of propositions; for if they lacked this property, they could not possibly be claims or assertions of any kind, they could not [ Page ] 53 represent anything, in which case they could not be true (/false). Regardless of how things stood in the world, propositions just would not have anything to say about those states of affairs. How then could we say of them that they were true (/false)? For surely a proposition is true only if it represents the world as it is. And just as surely the way things stand in reality is depicted as being thus and so only if something is being claimed about the way things so stand. We do not say that Ayer's memoir Part of My Life accurately represents his life—or rather, part of his life—if he is not mentioned, nothing is claimed about his person, and no comment at all is made about his comings or goings. A puzzle about parts Well then, what does it take to be a truth-claiming proposition? According to one venerable tradition—represented by Bertrand Russell (1903, §47-8), David Kaplan (1989), and others—a proposition is a complex whole; it has internal constituents (parts), and those constituents have a specific arrangement. This thesis can be developed along platonist or nominalist lines. Consider, first, a broadly platonist approach to the situation. Here, we suppose, things could go in a couple of directions. Following Russell, we might see (1) as an admixture of concrete particulars and abstract objects.4 On the concrete side of things, (1) would contain Quine himself as a constituent. But its other ingredients would include the (abstract) property of wisdom, along with the (abstract) exemplification relation Quine stands in to that property. This is a familiar story. The question, though, is whether it even slyly suggests that (1) might be about Quine. And it is hard to see that it does. Note first that whatever intentionality this proposition enjoys is inherited or derived; it will be a function of (l)’s parts, each of which is essential to it. If (1) is a Russellian proposition, for example, then if Quine had failed to exist, there would have been no such proposition as Quine is wise. Moreover, if any of the constituents of (1) were different than they are—say, if we substituted Obama for Quine—then an entirely different proposition would have resulted: certainly not one about Quine, and perhaps even with a differing truth value. So clearly, on the Russellian view, if (1) is about Quine at all, it can only be because it contains him as a constituent. But here, we think, there is confusion. Although it is not uncommon to see Russellian propositions presented as “complex abstract entities” (Pelham and Urquhart 1994, 307), the fact is they are neither abstract nor even propositions (at least as we are thinking of them). They are not claims or assertions that represent certain states of affairs; they are states of affairs. As the Russell scholar Anssi Korhonen notes: there is no condition in the world whose obtaining would be necessary for the truth of a [Russellian] proposition. Or, at any rate, this condition cannot be seen in any way distinct from the proposition itself. And this means that there is no gap between a propositions being true and somethings being the case: facts simply are (that is, are identical with) true propositions. (2009, 165) [ Page ] 54 In other words, Russellian “propositions” are actually the truth-conditions for what we are thinking of as truth bearers (propositions). On the Russellian view, (1) is not the claim that Quine has the property of being wise; rather, it is a concrete state of affairs that we can represent as follows: (1*) : Exemplification (Quine, wisdom).5 (1*) denotes a certain truthmaking fact, one consisting in the specific way Quine is related to wisdom. But as Vallicella points out, we must not confuse this with either the proposition Quine is wise or the state of affairs Quines being wise—both of which are in need of something to make them true (/actual).6 (1 *) simply designates the concrete fact that does that. This should make it clear that simply “plugging” Quine into a Russellian propo- sition like (1*) is not going to create a vehicle for representing the way Quine is. For (1*) just is the way Quine is. (1) represents the way things are; by contrast, (1*) denotes the things that are that way. Or think of it like this: Since Quine is not of or about anything, since he does not represent anything (even himself), the mere fact that something contains him will not make that thing about Quine. You might as well argue that Harvards philosophy department was about Quine because it contained him as a member. The point is: Just in himself, Quine, while impressive in many ways, is an intentional flop. Now here the platonist is not without reply. To avoid collapsing truthbearers into their truth-conditions, while at the same time securing intentionality, she might try removing Quine as a constituent of (1). Why not opt instead for a pure mix of platonic properties and relations? In that case, perhaps (1) would be rendered best as (1**) Being Quine is coinstantiated with being wise, a proposition consisting of two properties standing in the relation of coinstantiation. Since it does not include Quine, (1**) is distinct from the concrete state of affairs it represents—or at least so the platonist might claim. But does it represent? Why should we think that? Here we can imagine someone arguing as follows. Since being Quine uniquely characterizes Quine, how could it not be about him? His having this property guarantees that it is about him. Now of course we can all agree that (2) An object has the property being Quine if and only if it is Quine. But how does it follow that (3) Being Quine is about Quine? It does not follow. For the slide from (2) to (3) obviously confuses being P (where “P” names some property) with being about what has P. The two notions are not equivalent. Something could have P without P's being about what has it. For example, you could have being the author of Word and Object without that property being about you. If you are Quine, that property qualifies you all right; it is predicable of you, but it is not in itself of or about you; it is not directed upon you. Similarly, being wise is neither about nor represents any of its instances. This is especially evident when one [ Page ] 55 considers the fact that, for the platonist, there are worlds in which this property exists but nothing is wise. So we do not secure intentionality for a purely abstract property merely by pointing out that it has instances. Nor can we say being Quine is about Quine because it contains something that is: Quine himself. For as we have already noted, Quine is not about anything—even himself. To insist otherwise seems no more than a basic category mistake. So what is a platonist to say at this point? Here is a final possibility. We treat Quine is wise as a simple, brutely intentional Platonic Form—end of story. The problem, though, is that this hardly squares with what we all learned at Socrates’s knee. The Forms are not propositional.7 On the contrary, like the self-thinking Thought of Aristotle, they are wholly indifferent to their concrete instances. A Form—say, Circularity—is not directed toward any of the imperfect circles of the sort we routinely encounter. Rather, the “direction of fit”8 is entirely the other way around. In order to count as a circle, says Socrates, an object must “imitate” or “participate in” Circularity: being an enclosed line each point on which is equidistant from a fixed point (the center). It must possess a world-to-Form direction of fit, so to speak, to qualify as a thing of this kind. As a Platonic Form, however, Circularity is a mere ontological target, a certain standard of perfection to be approximated or achieved. And it can perform this function very nicely without possessing any direction of fit toward the lower world of concrete particulars. As a timeless, spaceless, metaphysical exemplar, Circularity is no more about the crop circle that mysteriously appeared on your front lawn this morning than the number five is about the fingers on your hand. So whereas we know by introspection that such things as thoughts, beliefs, and desires are intentional, we have no basis at all in reason or experience for thinking that Platonic Forms (including propositions, if we smuggle those in) are about anything. Why then are we tempted to think otherwise? For this reason, we believe. If you start with the idea that truthbearing requires intentionality, then (as Michael Jubien warns) it is very difficult not to confer a strictly derivative dose of intentionality upon something that is otherwise intentionally inert [that is, the abstract platonic proposition]. It may be very convenient to suppress this and proceed as if the entity had the intentional feature on its own, but doing so would be a matter of efficiency of thought, not ontology. (Jubien 2001, 53-4) We need propositions to do a certain amount of philosophical work. For the platonist, their job is to serve as truthbearers and objects of our propositional attitudes. It is therefore a matter of expediency to proceed as if they had the requisite intentional properties, but without taking the time to explain how this could be. But this is simply to smuggle intentional propositions into the nonintentional world of abstract Forms—a move that has all the appearance of theft over honest toil. Suppose we turn, then, to a nominalist approach to these matters; perhaps it will prove more promising. Now there are several varieties of nominalism with respect to propositions, and there is not the space here to deal with all of them.9 Instead, we will simply make some general remarks about what we take to be the core assumption [ Page ] 56 underlying the approach; and hopefully, this will offer hints about how to think of the versions we do not consider. Now we are operating, you recall, under the assumption that there is such a thing as truth, that there are truthbearers, and that a thing must have ofness or aboutness to possess truth. What sorts of things can the nominalist bring forward to fill the role of propositional truthbearer? Here sentences stand out as the most likely candidate. In the early Wittgenstein, for example, we are presented with the idea that proposi- tions are sentences or linguistic items of a sort. “’The totality of propositions,” he says, “is language” (2001, 22). Furthermore, a proposition (sentence) is said to represent reality; for a “proposition shows how things stand if it is true. And it says that they do so stand” (ibid., 25). It makes a claim about things, and it does so in part by virtue of its syntactic and logical form: “there must be exactly as many distinguishable parts [in the proposition] as in the situation that it represents” (ibid., 26). Let us assume all of this is in order. Then (1) is not an abstract object; it is the concrete sentence inscription “Quine is wise”—a linguistic item with parts (that is, “Quine,” “is,” and “wise”). And of course these parts have parts of their own (letters). The sentence "Quine is wise” is therefore a concrete particular; it is a string of shapes and characters. Call this string “S.” Why think that S is a primary bearer of truth? A truthbearer must represent things. But neither S nor its parts is about anything just in itself; shapes (even sequences of shapes) are not about things just by virtue of what they are. Accordingly, it is obvious that if S possesses any intentionality, it is borrowed or derived: not of course from its constituent parts, but rather (as Plantinga (2006, 17) notes) from our deciding to use it in a particular way, to express a proposition (that is, (1)) about Quines being wise. Indeed, Wittgenstein concedes this very point when he remarks, “a proposition is true if we use it to say that things stand in a certain way, and they do” (2001, 28, emphasis added). This makes it abundantly clear that the intentionality of a sentence lies outside of it. But where does this leave us? We have seen that “free-floating” abstract objects, that is, Platonic Forms existing in Platos heaven, are impotent to account for the intention- ality of (1); but concrete objects—ordinary particulars and linguistic entities—are really no better. Does that mean that (1) is not about Quine, that it makes no claim about him, and is therefore neither true nor false? Not at all. Fortunately, there is a better way forward. The problems faced by platonism and nominalism lead us to a third, more compelling view of the matter. The reason for the problems is by now obvious: You cannot force intentionality upon objects whose natures simply defy the imposition. Would it not be better, then, to begin with something known to be intentional, something on which intentionality does not have to be imposed? Indeed, there is a whole class of objects of this sort: ideas/concepts.10 By their very nature, ideas, regardless of who has them, are of or about things. John Locke actually refers to them as signs; and of course signs point to things. We speak of Descartes’s idea of a perfect being, Darwins ideas about Nature, and Russell’s idea of a proposition. It is incoherent to suppose that there are ideas that are not about anything. If it is not about anything, it is not an idea. This gives us a very handy solution to our puzzle about parts. That puzzle raised the question of how (1), the complex proposition Quine is wise, could be about Quine. On [ Page ] 57 the present suggestion, the answer is embarrassingly easy. (1) is about Quine because it contains a part (the idea of Quine) that is essentially about him. Neither a Platonic Form nor a concrete particular can pretend to credentials like this. A puzzle about arrangement But now a different puzzle emerges. Locating intentional parts—even the right parts—for (1) is crucial. But it does not automatically issue in a truth claim. For while ideas are certainly about things, they do not, strictly speaking, represent anything. Thus we cannot say that propositions are representative truthbearers because they are composed of true or false ideas. As John Locke observes, “truth and falsehood belong, in propriety of speech, only to propositions” (2004, 345), not to ideas. One can easily see why. For until “the mind passes some judgment on” its ideas, until it “affirms or denies something of them” (ibid.), there simply is no claim or assertion, no representation of reality as such. To judge or affirm that Quine is wise, to express that proposition, the ideas of Quine (Q) and wisdom (W) have to be joined to one another. To judge truly in this respect is to join Q and W in a way that reflects the actual relation of the things these ideas are about. So a proposition is far more than an unrelated list of items, as is the case, for example, with the ordered pair . The elements of this pair are indeed inten- tional objects; they are ideas o/things. Still, does not represent Quine as being wise. To do that, Q and W must be joined so that a specific claim is made. This requires that these ideas be put together in a very precise way. Now is indeed ordered since, by hypothesis, ≠ < W, Q>. But the thing to see is that it is not ordered in the right way. For while there is an asymmetrical “directionality” to the arrangement, it is not affirmative; there is not the slightest hint that we have a claim or assertion on our hands. For there is no predicational tie between Q and W. And given that Q and W are ideas, is not that sort of tie going to require a mental knot? So what explains this arrangement of ideas? Well, according to Thomas Aquinas, Every composition ... needs some composer. For, if there is composition, it is made up of a plurality, and a plurality cannot be fitted into a unity except by some composer. (1995, 1:103) Given this principle of composition, propositions will need a composer, since they are composed entities with an orderly arrangement of parts. But why is this necessary? Perhaps it will be helpful to remind ourselves of the obvious. Ideas, as we are viewing of them, occupy neither Plato’s detached realm of abstracta, nor Ayer’s world of empirically verifiable concreta. Ideas as such “cannot be seen, or touched, or smelled, or tasted, or heard” (Frege 1997, 224). Locke speaks of “those invisible ideas” of an individual “which his thoughts are made up of” (2004, 363). If we think about it, we can see that an essential property of an idea is that it is had or possessed. Ideas “need an owner” (Frege 1997, 334); they are ontological parasites on thinkers. [ Page ] 58 And just as there cannot be thoughts without a thinker, ideas (which are nothing but materials for thinking) cannot exist apart from the minds that have them. But then what better explanation could there be for the orderly arrangement of ideas than the mental activity of thinkers? The obvious conclusion to be drawn here is that the things properly said to be true or false (propositions) actually result from mental activity— from the joining or separating of ideas. Thus Locke once more: Every one’s experience will satisfy him, that the mind, either by perceiving or supposing the agreement or disagreement of any of its ideas, does tacitly within itself put them into a kind of proposition affirmative or negative, which I have endeavored to express by the terms putting together and separating. (2004, 510)11 Thus it follows straight away that propositions are mental effects. For propositions have parts, those parts are best construed as ideas, and their being properly related (that is, “fitted into” truth claims) requires a mental arranger. An objection and reply “If Q and W are just your ideas, then the proposition Quine is wise is only your thought or proposition. Indeed, there is no such thing as the proposition Quine is wise, in which case (as Frege (1997, 335-6) argues) no two people ever think the same thoughts. They only ever think their thoughts; nothing is in common.”12 Frege is on to something here. Propositions are not simply reducible to our thoughts (yours or mine). If they were, they would suffer from a deplorable fragility. And in any event, there just are not enough of us to think up all the propositions associated with, say, the natural numbers. Propositions are in some sense objective; even if we had not existed, they would have been none the worse off. So what is to be done? Freges way out here was to recognize what he called a “third realm”: a realm beyond the world of physical objects, beyond the realm of human ideas—in fact, a platonic realm of abstract thoughts without owners. But as we have already seen, such abstract platonic entities are no truthbearers; they lack all the necessary intentional ingredients. The proper thing to do, therefore, is to go one step further and recognize a fourth realm. Things belonging to this realm would have in common with human ideas that they were intentional objects. But like ordinary particulars, their existence would also be objective; that is, even if there were no human minds, these things would continue to exist nonetheless. Thus, to borrow Frege’s example, the Pythagorean Theorem is not just true from the time we discover it. It is more like a planet, which "even before anyone saw it, was in interaction with other planets” (Frege 1997, 337). Here we may happily agree. Propositions are indeed independent of human minds. Where Frege erred, however, was in thinking that propositions do not require owners. This is simply false if they are truthbearing claims composed of intentional parts. In this case, what we must grant, it seems, is a supranatural realm of divine ideas and thoughts, [ Page ] 59 not subject to the relativistic vagaries of human mental activity. The best way to look at things, perhaps, is to see we human beings as arranging our ideas—which are sometimes complete, but often only partial graspings of God’s ideas—into thoughts which approximate (to varying degrees) those of God himself. We can then reserve the term “proposition” for referring to Gods thoughts. The perils of unbridled theistic activism Naturally, much more remains to be said. But hopefully this fills in at least some of the details (and motivation) behind Morris and Menzel’s brief assertion that “we can characterize propositions as God’s thoughts.” However, we do not think that the activist project should be extended to properties and relations, thus, in what remains, we shall argue for a modified theistic activism (MTA). The linchpin of theistic activism is Morris and Menzel’s principle of Property- Concept Conflation (PCP): “All properties and relations are God’s concepts.” It is easy to see that this principle undermines basic attempts to explain the notion of a substance. Consider, for example, the bundle theory: conjoined with PCP, it leads to a form of Berkeleyan idealism. For suppose a material thing is nothing but a bundle of compresent multiply exemplifiable properties. Then if properties are God’s concepts, and if relations are God’s thinking concepts together, every material object is a mere collection of divine concepts or ideas, in which case we shall have to say that a substance changes just when God starts or stops “thinking together” His own concepts or ideas. Not only does this eradicate the material nature of reality, it smacks of an objectionable divine determinism (more severe than anything Calvinism has to offer). On a nominalist approach to bundles, things look only slightly better. Instead of bundling platonic properties, we might try tropes or property instances—such concrete entities as the wisdom of Socrates or this spot’s redness. A substance would then consist in a bundle of concrete particulars, thereby sidestepping the reduction of material things to abstract universals (and thus, by PCP, to divine ideas). Still, there is the matter of how these tropes hold together to form one substance. The typical expla- nation posits a basic, unanalyzable relation of compresence or collocation that serves as the ontological “glue” for these otherwise disparate tropes. According to PCP, however, this relation is not primitive; it is analyzable in terms of God’s conceptual activity. The tropes that comprise Socrates hold together because God thinks them together. At first glance, this strikes one as a tidy illustration of Paul’s words in Col. 1.17—that “in him all things hold together.” Strictly speaking, though, Paul does not say that things hold together because God thinks them together. In fact, would not the explanation go the other way around? God thinks of the tropes comprising Socrates as being compresent because He causes them to be so. In any event, it is (almost) trivial to say that God’s thinking these tropes together is the cause of their being together. For causation is a relation, and on PCP all relations are divine concepts. Therefore, to say that God causes trope compresence by thinking tropes together amounts to the tautologous [ Page ] 60 claim that God thinks of His thinking tropes together by thinking tropes together. The concept of causation as an extramental relation goes completely by the wayside here. Next, consider bare particular theory. Following Bergmann (1967, 22-6)—and more recently, Moreland (2001, 148-57), Pickavance (2009), and Sider (2006)—we might hold that a proper ontological assay of a substance (Socrates, let us say) must reference a bare particular, the relation of exemplification, and certain external property “ties.” To say that Socrates is human just means that the property of being human is “rooted in” Socrates as a constituent, but also “tied to” Socrates’s bare particular (call it “b”) by the exemplification relation. Unlike Socrates, however, b has no internal property constituents, and thus counts as a “thin” or “bare” particular. Proponents of this view go on to say that bare particulars have no categorical or kind-defining properties of their own; they only ground the properties of the concrete particulars of which they are constituents.13 But then given PCP, it looks as though Socrates is the result of Gods conceiving of & in terms of the divine concept being human, which is strange enough. However, matters are even worse; for b is a thing with no properties of its own, which (on PCP) simply means that God does not have a concept of it; in which case Socrates is the consequence of God’s conceiving of a thing of which He has no conception. It is not a coherent picture. Someone will object that we need only turn to Aristotelian substances and the problem dissolves. On the Aristotelian view, a concrete particular like Socrates is a basic entity; he is not “built up” from constituent properties “tied to” a constituent (bare) substratum. Rather, as Loux notes, the subject of ontic predication is Socrates himself. This is made possible by the simple fact that he belongs to a natural kind (that is, being human) that marks him out as a particular sort of thing, “countably distinct from other members of that kind and from members of other kinds” (2006, 113). Moreover, in virtue of being an instance of its proper kind, a concrete particular can be the subject for attributes—properties—that are external to its core being. So concrete particulars do have a structure that the ontologist can characterize: there is a core being or essence furnished by a kind and a host of properties that lie at the periphery of that core and, hence, are accidental to concrete particulars, (ibid.) Here there is no need to call up an incoherent (explanatorily prior) bare particular for purposes of property support. That has to be an advantage. The deeper issue, for whatever notion of substance used is that, given PCP, divine concepts are called upon to play a role that seems inimical to their nature. As essen- tially intentional mental objects, divine concepts (and concepts in general) mediate between mind and world.14 The primary role for properties, however, is that of making or structuring reality. As George Bealer observes, “[properties] play a fundamental constitutive role in the structure of the world” (1998a, 268). As we argued earlier, properties (that is, Platonic Forms) are intentional flops—they are not about anything, and essentially so. But, if divine concepts are called upon to play both the mediating and making role, it seems that they can only do so at a high cost in terms of theoretical economy. To see why consider: Divine concepts/properties are essentially intentional [ Page ] 61 (in their mediating role) and not intentional (in their making role). But, this picture seems incoherent. To make sense of this story, the activist employing PCP will need to argue that divine concepts/properties have (exemplify?) the following nature (essential property?): Being intentional when a constituent of thought, being nonintentional when not. Such a nature (property?) of divine concepts is surely unlovely (at best) and (at worst) smells of ad hocness.15 We say, best to leave properties and relations alone—they are sui generis, and admit their own ontological category. Can God create abstract objects? The version of MTA we wish to defend is a kind of modified platonic theism. Thus far we’ve argued that some abstracta are located within the divine mind (propositions and concepts) and some are external to God (properties and relations not exemplified by God). Thus, abstract objects exist in two realms: the divine mind16 and Plato’s heaven. This picture of the world opens us up to a number of worries, worries that we will attempt to discharge in the remainder of this chapter. If the existence of abstract objects is admitted into ones ontology, a prima facie problem arises for the traditional theist. The problem is this. Abstract objects, it seems, are best understood as uncreated entities. But, if abstract objects are uncreated, then God is not the creator of everything, a view that appears unacceptable to the tradi- tional theist constrained by Scripture and tradition. Some platonists (e.g. Peter van Inwagen (2009)) argue that theists need not worry—there is no actual tension between traditional theism and the existence of abstract objects since abstract objects are not the kinds of things that can enter into causal relationships. It is our judgment that if sense can be given to the causality by which one necessary being (God) would cause another necessary being (abstract objects) to exist, then there is no good reason to think that God could not create abstract objects and hence, no good reason to think that abstract objects cannot enter into causal relations.17 Assume anti-reductionism regarding causation.18 Anti-reductionism is not the view that causation is primitive. Primitivism regarding causation denies that there are any concepts more basic than causation. All we wish to endorse here is that there are no noncausal terms that can adequately explicate the notion of causation. Given anti-reductionism regarding causation, God’s creating abstracta can be understood as follows: (C^) God caused abstract object P if He brought it about that P exists. (C^) specifies a plausible account of causation in which such creation is possible (in which a sufficient, but not necessary condition for such creation is realized). Still, one might object: (CA) is hardly illuminating in terms of how God creates abstract objects. Specifically, the right-hand side of the conditional doesn’t explain the left-hand side— as it stands, they are virtually synonyms at face value. Fortunately, we’ve already seen [ Page ] 62 a more illuminating anti-reductive account of how God causes abstract objects, the theistic activism of Morris and Menzel: (CTA) God caused abstract object P if P is (i) a constituent of God’s mind (ii) brought about by the activity of thinking. We also think that the following is an acceptable understanding of God’s creating abstracta: (CMTA) God caused abstract object P if P is brought about by the activity of divine willing. (CMTA) allows that God creates abstract objects wholly distinct from His being— existing in a platonic heaven even. And if (CTA) and/or (CMTA) are possibly true, then it is reasonable to think that God can indeed create abstract objects. We argue that He has in fact done so.19 Divine bootstrapping? But, can our MTA avoid the charge of incoherence because of divine bootstrapping? Recall that the bootstrapping worry is usually advanced as follows: "God has properties. If God is the creator of all things, then God is the creator of His properties. But God can’t create properties unless He already has the property of being able to create a property. Thus, we are ensnared in a vicious explanatory circle. God causes His nature to exist—a nature He must already possess to do the causing.” We think that the incoherency worry due to divine bootstrapping can be successfully avoided by endorsing the following two claims: [A] God’s essential platonic properties exist a se (i.e. they are neither created nor sustained by God, yet they inhere in the divine substance); and [B] Substances are Aristotelian. Endorsement of claim [A] allows us to avoid the unwanted view that God creates His own nature; claim [B] ensures that the divine substance is a fundamental unity that is the final cause of its constituent metaphysical parts (including divine concepts and essential properties)—which ensures God’s ultimacy. Thus, the divine substance, along with all of its essential properties exists a se and everything distinct from God (that is, everything external to God’s borders) is created and sustained by God. What about the rest of the platonic horde: numbers, sets, quantifiers, states of affairs, and possible worlds? No doubt each of these alleged abstracta requires a paper in its own right. However, if our discussion of MTA has taught us anything, we should not expect any one approach here to single-handedly resolve the issues raised by the platonic horde and its relationship to God. Still, we have good reason to think that each of these abstracta can be safely brought either into the mind of God or located in Platos heaven, without violating God’s aseity or sovereignty. Thus, one kind of platonic [ Page ] 63 theist can have it all: an attractive (realist) theory of the mind-world-language nexus and fidelity to Scripture and tradition. Notes 1 This is not quite true of course. Sets are presumably abstract; however, arguably, some sets—e.g. Obama’s singleton—exist in only those worlds in which Obama does. For more on the contingency of sets, see Alvin Plantinga (1976, 146-7). 2 Plantinga now thinks that abstract objects can enter into causal relationships, see (2011,32). 3 But see the Introduction where they are nicely laid out. 4 Compare Russell: “Whatever may be an object of thought, or may occur in any true or false proposition ... I call a term.... A man, a moment, a number, a class, a relation, a chimaera, or anything else that can be mentioned, is sure to be a term” (1903, 43). 5 Following D. W. Mertz, we use the colon locution for the operator “The fact that.” 6 On the importance of distinguishing between concrete and abstract states of affairs, see William F. Vallicella (2000, 237). 7 As Matthew McGrath notes, if Plato believed in propositional Forms, he could have had Socrates solve the problem of how a false belief (e.g. in Pegasus) could actually be about something by saying that there is an object of belief here: the (false) abstract proposition Pegasus exists. However, no such proposal is even considered. See McGrath (2012, §1). 8 A term coined by J. L. Austin. See Searle (1998, 101). 9 For an excellent overview of nominalist options, see Michael Loux (2006, 130-9). 10 We shall use the terms “ideas” and “concepts” synonymously. 11 Locke actually distinguishes two sorts of propositions: mental (thoughts) and verbal (sentences). Both are composed of signs, he says: the former consist of ideas, the latter of words. Here we focus exclusively on mental propositions. For as we noted earlier, even if we can speak of sentences as being true or false, it is only in a derivative sense. 12 Thus Michael Jubien: “Somehow or other, [conceptualism] has to make room for the fact that you and I can 'believe the same thing’” (1997, 52). 13 Compare Moreland and Pickavance: “the properties said to be necessary for bare particulars are not genuine properties; these include simplicity, particularity, unrepeatability, and those of the three categories of transcendental, disjunction, and negative properties” (2003, 10). 14 Dallas Willard states, “[concepts] form the ‘bridge’ that connects a thought and its object” (1999, 13). 15 Part of the ad hoc character of the necessary fix is that (as we mentioned earlier) it is typically thought that properties/Forms are wholly indifferent to their concrete instances, but now the activist is forced to admit otherwise. One of us has argued that it seems possible for the theistic activist to employ PCP, even if it is unlovely and uneconomical—at any rate, it is not logically impossible. See Gould (2011a). 16 Below we will allow that God exemplifies properties and stands in relations to constituent parts, thus this first realm of abstract objects is best understood as the divine substance (of which the mind is a part). [ Page ] 64 17 We are not alone in this, e.g. Plantinga thinks that theistic activism gives us good reason to think that abstract objects can enter into causal relations: “[if] sets, numbers and the like ... are best conceived as divine thoughts ... then they stand to God in the relation in which a thought stands to a thinker .... If so, then [abstract objects] stand in a causal relation” (2011a, 32). 18 Anti-reductionism regarding causation is plausible, enjoys independent motivation, and has been ably defended recently by inter alia John Carroll (2010) and James Woodward (1990). Typical arguments for anti-reductionism involve (i) detailing the repeated failures of reductive analysis; (2) the fact that there is a sparse base of noncausal concepts that can be employed in providing a reductive analysis; and (iii) the case of preemption. 19 Granted, there are other issues looming in the background that would need to be addressed in articulating a robust doctrine of God’s creation of abstract objects, including providing an explication of eternal creation—for in the case of God creating everlasting abstract objects, the cause is not temporally prior to its effect. This topic would require another paper, but for now let us state that many contemporary philosophers working on the metaphysics of causation agree that causation need not involve reference to the relation of temporal priority. Indeed contemporary discussions of causal asymmetry deal routinely with cases in which cause and effect are simultaneous and, we are told, physics takes seriously the possibility of backwards directed time-travel and the accompanying backwards directed causation. See John Carroll (2010) and Huemer and Kovitz (2003). For a robust defense of the claim that God can create abstract objects, see Gould 2013. [ Page ] 65 Response to Paul M. Gould and Richard Brian Davis Keith Yandell In my first reply, I wish to say something that I will not repeat. It has been a pleasure to read the papers of my colleagues. I have learned from them and respect their positions. However much I sometimes disagree with views expressed, I do not think our discussion concerns a point of Christian orthodoxy. I turn to putting my points briefly, concerning both Professor Gould’s fine introduction and the fuller essay by Gould/Davis. Regarding the Augustine passage quoted by Professor Gould (17, note 4), what he spoke strongly against was holding the view that God has to appeal to Platonic Forms in order to have a recipe for making things. It is no part of propositionalism to say that. Modified Theistic Activism (MTA) holds that some abstracta (e.g. propositions, concepts, and maybe more) are the product of Gods intellectual activity, but others (such as properties and relations distinct from God) are the product of Gods creative activity, but not His intellectual activity. MTA is “modified” in another way as well: Those properties (and relations) essential to God exist a se within the divine substance as uncreated entities, thus waiving a uniform account of properties (and relations). Whether God strictly creates propositions is another matter. If propositions are the propositional contents of God’s thoughts, then if God is necessarily omniscient, having those thoughts are part of, or at least entailed by, God’s nature. If necessary omniscience requires being unrelentingly aware of every truth, then God does not create them; thinking them is part of, or at least entailed by, God’s nature. If necessary omniscience permits merely being able to bring every true proposition to mind without always having it “in mind,” then without independent abstracta, God must recreate whatever propositions are not “in mind.” This of course is not possible if God is eternal rather than everlasting, and the eternalist will embrace an eternal unrestricted attendance of all truths in the hall of divine thought. Suppose there are abstract objects. Then consider the sovereignty issue. Either it is possible that abstracta are caused, or it is not. If it is, then God created them. If it is not, then it no more restricts God’s sovereignty that God did not create them than that God cannot make other contradictions true. Either way, on any logically consistent notion of sovereign creation, God is sovereign regarding creating if and only if, for everything X that exists, is not God, and can be created, X is created by God. The claim that abstract objects are ideas necessarily had by a necessarily existing God cannot be literally true. Granting that there is an abstract-versus-concrete distinction, abstract objects are not concrete. God is a concrete being. The ideas of a concrete being are concrete, as it is that in virtue of which they have propositional content. Hence abstract objects are not God’s ideas. The person who says that abstract [ Page ] 66 objects are ideas in the divine mind is saying that what exists instead o/abstract objects are ideas necessarily had by a necessarily existing God. There is a problem with saying that propositions are assertions as opposed to saying that they are what can be asserted. “Blueberries are not moonbeams” is a perfectly fine assertion, but I doubt that anyone (including God) has asserted it. The idea that God creates abstract objects that are distinct from God and neces- sarily exist has attracted some. I doubt that a necessarily existing thing can be created by, or be dependent on, anything, but I waive that. Strictly, what must be meant here is that God emanates necessarily existing abstracta (see my lead essay for further discussion). To say that God necessarily has some property Q, or necessarily engages in some activity A, or necessarily undergoes some process P resulting in the existence of X, is to say that God does so eternally or everlastingly. Given that abstracta are distinct from God, and exist necessarily, God too must exist necessarily. If God emanates abstracta, God is not free to refrain from so doing. So God cannot fail to be a creator. On this view, divine sovereignty does not allow God to be otherwise than being the maker of one kind of thing. Further, God depends for God’s existence on there being the abstracta that God must create. This is not merely a case in which, since any necessary truth entails every other, the denial of any necessary truth entails the denial of any other. If God cannot but produce abstracta, then their absence would entail God’s absence without appeal to entailment among necessary truths, even assuming that God exists is a necessary truth. Taking “world” in a very broad sense, propositions represent the way that the world is, and are true if the world is that way. They are thus about the world whose content determines their truth value. It is not obvious that propositions are made up of concepts as sentences are made up of words. Consider the claim that S has the concept of being a cow insofar as S knows what is true if and only if there are cows. Then concepts are propositional abilities that persons have, or the results of using those abilities, and propositions are primary. Appeal to tradition is not so straightforward as assumed. MTA is inconsistent with the traditional divine simplicity doctrine. Many contemporary Christian philosophers reject divine eternity. Does this raise questions about MTA and divine everlastingism? Why, and to what extent? I do not think Scripture is against propositionalism. The question of the existence of propositions is a technical philosophical issue and on one view such things are necessarily not causable. The dispute as to whether that view, combined with the view that there are propositions, can be held by Christians who think consistently is contro- versial—too philosophically, theologically, and exegetically controversial for any “side” to justifiably claim exclusive exegetical basis for its view. Greg Welty Anyone reading the Gould/Davis chapter and my own can see that our respective approaches to these matters have much in common. We have both argued that the [ Page ] 67 intrinsic/derived intentionality distinction is relevant to critiquing nominalism, and that the intrinsic intentionality of propositions is best explained as the intrinsic intentionality of thoughts. In addition (going beyond the scope of my own chapter), I agree with Gould/Davis that the Russellian platonist analysis of propositions fails, that unbridled theistic activism (TA) is perilous, and that the “God cannot create necessary beings” objection to TA is bogus. Despite all this, here are a few areas of potential disagreement. Gould/Davis claim that conceptualism “does a much better job than its closest competitors (platonism and nominalism) in accounting for the truthbearing nature of propositions” (52). While their case against nominalism seems secure, their case against platonism needs some work. First, while I agree that the Russellian analysis fails for the reasons noted, Gould/Davis seem to think that the only platonist alter- native to Russell is to “treat Quine is wise as a simple, brutely intentional Platonic Form—end of story” (55). They continue: "The problem, though, is that this hardly squares with what we all learned at Socrates’s knee. The Forms are not propositional” (55). But this criticism unwarrantably restricts platonist options to whatever Plato actually wrote. Why can't the modern platonist stipulate that there are non-spatiotem- poral, intentional truthbearing entities—the kind expressed by sentences and serving as the referents of that-clauses, among other things—and be done with it? What, exactly, is the problem here? Platonists simply infer that there must be such entities because this ontological specification best satisfies the functional concept of “propo- sition” that emerges from realist arguments for propositions. What Plato said about “Forms” doesn’t matter. Second, Gould/Davis claim that “whereas we know by introspection that such things as thoughts, beliefs, and desires are intentional, we have no basis at all in reason or experience for thinking that Platonic Forms (including propositions, if we smuggle those in) are about anything” (55). But surely platonists will say that we do have reason for thinking that propositions are about things: The realist arguments give us reason to think there are such intentional entities. Following Jubien, Gould/Davis apparently think that platonists start with an “intentionally inert” entity, “the abstract Platonic proposition,” and then they “confer a strictly derivative dose of intentionality upon” (55) it. (They “smuggle intentional propositions into the nonintentional world of abstract Forms” (55). They “force intentionality upon objects whose natures simply defy the imposition” (56). “Platonic entities ... lack all the necessary intentional ingre- dients” (58).) But as far as I can tell, platonists just infer that there are these intentional entities, and that is that. Who says these entities must start out “intentionally inert,” like bits of graphite or ink, only to be baptized by aboutness later? Third, Gould/Davis claim that “Given [Aquinas’s] principle of composition, propo- sitions will need a composer, since they are composed entities with an orderly arrangement of parts” (57). But while this would pave the way for conceptualism, it’s not clear why we should regard propositions as “composed entities with an orderly arrangement of parts.” This is part and parcel of Russell’s (failed) analysis of propo- sitions. Must it be an element of any platonist account? Why? (Propositions make reference to entities. But are they therefore composed of parts? One might as well say [ Page ] 68 that since God refers to entities He is composed of parts. More argument is needed here, I think.) Fourth, Gould/Davis claim that platonists don’t take the time to “explain how” propositions can have “the requisite intentional properties” (55). This is a worry for platonists, but I wonder how strong it is. I agree that “it is incoherent to suppose that there are ideas that are not about anything. If it is not about anything, it is not an idea” (56). But does stating this “explain how” thought has intentionality? Are we not saying that thoughts are intentional by definition? In this respect, do platonists claim any less for their entities? In contrast to all this, my alternative case against platonism and for conceptualism involves conceding that platonists can easily infer their denizens of the abstract realm from the various realist arguments on offer (I canvassed four). The problem is not that their entities are not intentional or are not composed of parts, but that their entities multiply ontological kinds beyond explanatory necessity. This appeal to simplicity is not open to Gould/Davis, as they are happy to posit “Platos heaven” in addition to the divine thoughts. About modified theistic activism (MTA) I will explain just one worry. MTA is “modified” in order to avoid bootstrapping worries. It retains the characteristic claim of TA that abstract objects like propositions and properties causally depend upon God. He “brings about” these things in some sense of nonreductive causation. But MTA exempts God’s essential properties from this causal process, so that He is not stuck creating His nature. This is certainly an improvement. But as Matthew Davidson has pointed out (1999, 288-90), even if God only creates propositions the bootstrapping worries remain. If God causes the proposition God exists to exist, He causes its essence (which includes the property being true) to be exemplified. Thus, in causing this proposition to exist, He makes it true, and thus God causes His own existence. In response, Gould/Davis could further restrict MTA, such that propositions (or at least the troublesome ones) also inhabit platonic heaven rather than being caused by God. But then this frustrates their sustained, carefully crafted case that platonic proposi- tions are inherently unworkable. I would make the change in the other direction (surprise, surprise!): The relation between propositions and God is one of constitutive dependence rather than causal dependence.1 William Lane Craig Gould/Davis’s modified theistic activism is a hybrid view: Conceptualism with respect to propositions and absolute creationism with respect to properties and relations. Their essay, like Weltys, illustrates the way in which the two different debates over so-called nominalism (see pp. 115-16 of my lead essay) can run together. Consider first their absolute creationism. They affirm that God causes abstract objects (like properties) that are wholly distinct from His being. The key question in assessing their view is whether they successfully answer the bootstrapping objection. In reply to the objection, they endorse two claims (62): [ Page ] 69 [A] God’s essential platonic properties exist a se (i.e. they are neither created nor sustained by God, yet they inhere in the divine substance) and [B] Substances are Aristotelian. Their view seems to be that God does not stand in a relation of exemplification to certain platonic properties existing extra se, in virtue of which He is powerful, wise, good, and so forth. Rather God just is a powerful, wise, good substance, and any properties He has are immanent universals. But this Aristotelian view seems to me to yield the palm of victory to the anti-platonist. For this just is anti-platonism with respect to God. But then no justification remains for giving things the “ontological assay” that the platonist wants to give. Things can be powerful or wise or brown without being so in virtue of standing in an exemplification relation to an abstract property. Once the absolute creationist has gone this route, no rationale remains for platonism about properties. If this is not their view, then I frankly do not understand it.2 Now consider their conceptualism with respect to propositions. I applaud their emphasis on the centrality of intentionality. Any aboutness associated with either sentence tokens or abstract propositions is derivative, the result of their being used by intentional agents. Now considerations of intentionality immediately raise the question of the ontological status of intentional objects. It is a datum of experience that we often think about things that do not exist—Santa Claus, the accident that was prevented, the hole in my sock, last summer's vacation, and so on. Gould/Davis tell us, “It is incoherent to suppose that there are ideas that are not about anything” (56). This was a characteristic emphasis of Alexius Meinong’s Theory of Objects (Gegenstandstheorie). According to Meinong the intentional objects of some of our ideas are nonexistent objects. Do Gould/Davis mean to endorse Meinong’s view? If so, then why not say with the neo-Meinongian that abstract objects like propositions, numbers, and properties are nonexistent objects? Then divine aseity and creatio ex nihilo remain inviolate. On the other hand, if they mean to endorse a view of intentionality more akin to Meinong’s teacher Brentano, according to which intentionality is not a relation between a mental state and an object, but a monadic property of a mental state (e.g. I have the property thinking-of-Santa Claus), then why not say with the anti-realist that our ability to think of propositions, numbers, and properties does not imply that there actually exist such objects? Gould/Davis would say that we need something more than mere sentence tokens to serve as truthbearers. But why? The truth-predicate “is true” may be seen simply as a device of semantic ascent which enables us to talk about a statement rather than to assert the statement itself. For example, rather than say that God is triune, we can ascend semantically and say that it is true that God is triune. Similarly, whenever the truth-predicate is employed, we can descend semantically and simply assert the statement said to be true. For example, rather than say that it is necessarily true that [ Page ] 70 God is self-existent, we can descend semantically and simply assert that, necessarily, God is self-existent. Nothing is gained or lost through such semantic ascent and descent Why is a device of semantic ascent useful or needed in natural language? The answer is that the truth-predicate serves the purpose of blind truth ascriptions. In many cases we find ourselves unable to assert the statement or statements said to be true because we are incapable of rehearsing them due to their sheer numerosity, as in “Every theorem of Peano arithmetic is true,” or because we are ignorant of the relevant statements, as in “Everything stated in the documents is true.” In theory even blind truth ascriptions are dispensable if we substitute for them infinite disjunctions or conjunctions like “Either p or q or r or ... .” While such infinite disjunctions and conjunctions are unknowable by us, they are known to an omniscient deity, so that God has no need of blind truth ascriptions. Hence, He has no need of semantic ascent and, hence, no need of the truth-predicate. Finally, I am not convinced that Gould/Davis’s conceptualism can avoid collapse into anti-realism. I concur with Oppy (pp. 178-9 that thoughts are not abstract objects nor are they composed of abstract objects (ideas). Otherwise, it seems unintelligible to say that thoughts (abstract objects) exist in God’s mind. They are concrete mental events or states. Like psychologism, against which Frege inveighed, divine conceptualism, as Welty rightly sees (p. 90), is really an anti-platonic realism. As different versions of concrete realism (see Fig. 1 on p. 40), psychologism and conceptualism posit mental tokens rather than physical tokens in the place of abstracta. But the anti-realist theist also believes that God has thoughts to which truth can be ascribed. So what gain is there in conceptualism? One may as well just rest content with anti-realism. Scott A. Shalkowski Gould/Davis begin with the wholly sensible task of asking and answering the crucial, but often overlooked, questions regarding propositions. What are proposi- tions supposed to be? What are they supposed to do? In their critique of platonism, they bring together what philosophers say in its favor, showing that even though it is a highly recommended philosophical view, it cannot perform the central tasks for which it was invented. If one does not accept an identity theory of truth (McDowell 1994; Hornsby 1997), then there must be some distinctions between the ways things are and the ways things are represented to be, even for truths. Their discussion of Russellian propositions containing Quine (himself) and non-Russellian propositions containing being Quine highlights the idea that things in themselves do not represent. Purely ontological accounts of representation and truth fail, whether platonist or nominalist. Their rejection of nominalism, however, is too swift. No concrete item intrinsically represents, but nominalists need not think that they do. All that follows from the intentionality requirement on representation is that there are no unintended claims and, hence, no unintended truths. Nominalists and the divine conceptualists are in league here. [ Page ] 71 Nominalists might part company when Gould/Davis insist that “propositions are mental effects” (58). The problem is not that propositions are parasites (57). All hangs on the nature of the parasitism. If the extension of “proposition” goes no further than beliefs held, assertions or claims made, then the differences are merely stylistic. Gould/Davis want to make propositions God’s thoughts. Nominalists need not object. Insofar as we can make sense of the common philosophical vocabulary, God is neither abstract nor physical but is concrete. So, Gods thoughts are no less within the nominalist's framework than are ours. What separates nominalists from MTAists is whose intentions are relevant to our comprehensive philosophical accounting of things. Nominalists may agree that if truths antedate the creatures sufficient to intend the relevant signage, then human signage is insufficient. If one can sometimes think the same thought as another, then those thoughts cannot be wholly private and the acts of thinking must have something in common. Two pauses, though. Why think that we do, as we commonly say, think the same thought? Why is it not sufficient that you think that Quine is wise and so do I? Both platonists and MTAists share the idea that besides (a) Quine being wise, (b) you and your thoughts, (c), me and my thought, there must still be an object—a represen- tation—to which each of us and our thoughts must be related. Nominalists deny that there are sufficient grounds for thinking this. We can, if we like, say that you and I think the same thing when you think Quine is wise and so do I, but each of us repre- sents things to ourselves—and to others when we decide to go public that Quine is wise. To the extent that we have ideas and we intend to direct them as signs one way and not others, we simply intend the relevant mental state and its public exhibition to be directed toward what is (Quine) and how he is (wise). No grounds are apparent to me for taking “the same” to mean anything more, ontologically speaking, than that you and I each think/speak/write about Quine and, furthermore, that he is wise. If this is what “the same” comes to here, then nominalists agree that there are proposi- tions (though the claim will invite inevitable confusion), but deny that there is another object involved whether external or internal to the mind of God. If one insists that “the same” requires an object besides Quine and any of our signage relevant to isolating and characterizing him, then nominalists parts company and ask why “the same” signals anything more than what the nominalist already recognizes—you and I agree about Quines wisdom. If the nominalist's complaint is answered sufficiently, the identity secured by each of us thinking God’s thought that Quine is wise brings with it a new problem. My thought, on this account, is no longer primarily related to Quine (though it may be so directed). Lapsing into metaphor perhaps, my thought must be God’s, where God’s thought is “in” God’s mind. Now, I am no more in God’s mind—even when God is thinking of me—than Quine is in mine when I think of him, lest the view lapse into the Berkleyan idealism Gould/Davis seek to avoid (59). How exactly is it that the very same thought that is God’s is mine? If my thought is a physical going-on in my brain, I do not see how it can be, but even if my thought is in my mind beyond space and time, I still do not see how my thought can literally be God’s. Platonists under-tell [ Page ] 72 the story regarding how we are related to sui generis platonic objects and MTAism requires something beyond the assertion that we all think the same (divine) thoughts when we think anything. Since the argument for MTAism begins with the failure of platonists to put the whole of their platonistic picture together into a coherent whole by incorporating it with what we think we know about truth, truthmakers, etc., MTAism must not commit the same error. Since we now have God, Quine, you, and me involved, we require a bit more to put the pieces together. How do I get access to God’s thought? How is my getting access to that thought different from when God reveals to me that Quine is wise? How is it different when I falsely (let us say) think that Quine is foolish when God thinks (truly) that Quine is wise? When I think that Quine is wise, I do not think that Quine is foolish. If propositions are Gods thoughts, then assuming that mistaken beliefs whose contents are propositions are possible, then God must think Quine foolish, since there is no independent proposition for God to entertain, while also thinking him wise. How, exactly, does all of that go, especially the identity claim? Graham Oppy Gould and Davis defend a conceptualist account of propositions: They claim (*) that propositions are thoughts in the mind of God. In arguing for (*), they make a number of controversial assumptions, including: (1) that there are propositions; (2) that propositions are claims or assertions; (3) that propositions are truthbearers; (4) that propositions are essentially intentional objects; and (5) that propositions are mind- dependent entities. Ad (1): In the context of a general inquiry into abstract objects, it cannot just be assumed that there are propositions. After all, we might decide that we should be fictionalists about them. And it is not hard to see the utility that talk of propositions brings even if there are no propositions. In particular, there are various kinds of generalizations that are much more easily stated if we allow ourselves to talk about propositions as objects. Consider for example: If the Pope says it, then it must be true. Without the fiction of propositions, we would be left with an infinite conjunction, or an infinite number of instances of a schema, or the like. Or consider: Mary believes what Tom doubts. Even if we could have said Mary believes that so-and-so but Tom doubts that so-and-so, the wheels of conversation are greased if we pretend that there are propositions over which we can quantify (and, in any case, we can say Mary believes what Tom doubts even if there is no sentence of the form Mary believes that so-and-so but Tom doubts that so-and-so that is available to us). At the very least, in the light of these observations, a case needs to be made that we should prefer realism to fictionalism about propositions. . Ad (2): If there are such things as propositions, then propositions are the contents of claims and assertions. If I assert that it is warm, then the content of my assertion is the proposition that it is warm. If I claim that it is warm, then the content of my claim is the proposition that it is warm. But, equally, if I wonder whether it is warm, then [ Page ] 73 the content of my wondering is the proposition that it is warm. And yet, of course, my wondering involves no claim or assertion. This seems to me to be sufficient to establish that, if there are such things as propositions, then propositions are not assertions or claims. Moreover, it also seems to me to be sufficient to establish that propositions do not represent reality as being some particular way: rather, someone’s taking an appro- priate attitude towards a proposition may represent reality as being some particular way. If, for example, I assert that it is warm, then my assertion represents (local) reality as being warm; but if I wonder whether it is warm, then my wondering does not represent (local) reality as being any particular way. Ad (3): If there are such things as propositions, it may be so that there is some sense in which propositions are truthbearers. But there are other good candidates for truthbearers, and there are important questions to ask about which candidates are base-level truthbearers. Some truthbearers are verbal tokenings. If I say, at a particular time and place, that it is warm, then, if it is warm at that particular time and place, I speak truly. More carefully: If I produce a verbal token—“It is warm”—at a particular time and place, then, if it is warm at that particular time and place, I speak truly in producing that particular token. Of course, my verbal token must be produced with appropriate intent: If I produce my token while acting on the stage, then, even if it is warm on the stage, I shall likely not have spoken truly in producing my token. And doubtless there are other qualifications that should also be introduced. But, at the very least, it is often so that I speak truly, in producing a particular verbal token, just in case things are as my verbal tokenings represents them to be. Some truthbearers are other kinds of tokenings. If I produce a written token—“It is warm”—at a particular time and place, then, if it is warm at that time and place, I write truly in producing that particular written token (given the satisfaction of other relevant conditions). If I produce a particular mental token—“It is warm”—at a particular time and place, then, if it is warm at that time and place, I think truly in producing that particular mental token (perhaps given the satisfaction of other relevant conditions). And there may be other kinds of tokenings that are also truthbearers. On the view that I favor, tokenings are the base-level truthbearers, and—perhaps— tokens and propositions are derivative truthbearers. (Whether verbal tokenings are more basic truthbearers than mental tokenings is a question that need not be decided here.) If there are propositions, then tokenings involve both tokens and propositions— “vehicles” and “contents”—but the base-level truthbearers are the tokenings, and not either the tokens or the propositions. (A view to which I might be forced to retreat is that tokenings, tokens, and propositions are all truthbearers, none of which should be supposed to be more fundamental truthbearers than the others.) Ad (4): Tokenings are intentional—tokenings are about things. So, for example, thought tokenings are intentional—thought tokenings are about things. If I have a thought that Quine is wise, then I have a thought about Quine. If we think of my thought tokening as being a tokening of “Quine is wise,” then my thought tokening is about Quine because it contains a tokening of “Quine” and—in appropriate condi- tions—tokenings of “Quine” are about Quine (because they refer to Quine). Given that tokenings are intentional, and that propositions are the objects (or contents) [ Page ] 74 of tokenings, we can allow that there is a sense in which propositions are inten- tional objects—but it seems to me that this intentionality of propositions is clearly “secondary” or “derivative.” (If you are worried about talk of thought tokenings, it should be clear that I can run exactly the same line in connection with verbal tokenings. Verbal tokenings are intentional, and their intentionality depends upon the referential properties of sub-tokenings of names, pronouns, and so forth.) Ad (5): Given the distinction between tokenings, tokens, and propositions, it is, I think, quite clear that, while tokenings are mind-dependent objects, tokens and propositions need not be. Certainly, once produced, written and verbal tokens are not mind-dependent; but, if there are mental tokens then, of course, they are mind- dependent. However, crucially, if there are propositions, then there is simply no reason at all to suppose that propositions are mind-dependent. If there are propositions, then propositions are the contents of tokens involved in particular tokenings—but, as just noted, it is the tokenings that are the clearly mind-dependent entities. Ad (*): As argued in my original paper, the claim, that propositions are thoughts in the mind of God, is ambiguous. Thoughts can be, variously, tokenings, tokens, or contents. For reasons already argued, propositions cannot be tokenings or tokens in the mind of God: Each of these suppositions simply involves a category mistake. But, if God exists, and there are propositions, while propositions will be the contents of divine thought tokenings, propositions simply will not be ontologically dependent upon those divine thought tokenings. After all, propositions could not play the role of being the contents or objects of divine thought tokenings unless they were ontologi- cally independent of those divine thought tokenings. Notes 1 Davidson’s argument (ibid.) seems to preclude a TA account of possible worlds as well. If God creates them, He causes God exists to be true in all possible worlds. Since this includes the actual world, God causes His own existence in the actual world. 2 Neither do I understand Gould/Davis’s claim that “[B] ensures that the divine substance is a fundamental unity that is the final cause of its constituent metaphysical parts (including divine concepts and essential properties)—which ensures God’s ultimacy” (62). If by “final cause” they mean a final cause in Aristotle’s sense, then I do not understand how God is the final cause of His parts. If they mean by “final” something like ultimate, then they seem to countenance that God is the efficient cause of Himself—the ultimate bootstrapping trick! [ Page ] 75 Response to Critics Paul M. Gould and Richard Brian Davis The Bootstrapping Worry Craig, Welty, and to a lesser extent, Yandell, press worries regarding MTA’s suggested way out of the bootstrapping objection. In our lead essay, we suggest that the bootstrapping objection can be avoided by endorsing two claims: [A] God’s essential platonic properties exist a se (i.e. they are neither created nor sustained by God, yet they inhere in the divine substance); and [B] Substances are Aristotelian. In his reply, Craig suggests “this Aristotelian view ... yields the palm of victory to the anti-platonist” (69) for “things can be powerful or wise or brown without being so in virtue of standing in an exemplification relation to an abstract property” (69). Craig admits that if his characterization is not accurate, then he does not understand our view. We concur—his characterization is not accurate and we welcome this oppor- tunity to further clarify our position. Minimally, to exemplify a property is to possess or have a property. Broadly speaking, two distinct styles of metaphysical explanation—best explained in terms of the concept of “ontological structure” (van Inwagen 2011)—can be discerned for understanding property possession by ordinary concrete objects. The Relational Ontologist thinks that ordinary concrete objects have no ontological structure; that the only parts an ordinary concrete object has are its everyday mereological parts; properties are possessed/tied-to/exemplified by the substances that have them even as they stand "apart” from them. The Constituent Ontologist thinks that ordinary concrete objects have an ontological structure; that the familiar objects of our everyday experience have constituent metaphysical and physical parts; properties enter into the being of the substances that have them by being nonmereological parts of it (see also Wolterstorff 1991). Both approaches tell us that substances exhibit whatever character they have in virtue of properties had by it. Properties characterize substances. How, on either approach, is property possession assayed? Consider the following sentence: (1) God is divine. On the relational approach, (1) can be further analyzed as: (2) God exemplifies being divine. God stands in a relation or tie to the property being divine. On the constituent approach, (1) can be further analyzed as: [ Page ] 76 (3) Being divine inheres in God as a constituent. and (4) God’s individuator exemplifies being divine. Sentences (3) and (4) are understood as follows: the divine substance (that is, God) has as a constituent the property being divine. Further, the property being divine is exemplified by an individuator that is also a constituent of the divine substance (perhaps a bare or thin particular).1 The property inheres in the substance and is exemplified by some individuator (which also inheres in the substance). Thus, Craig is mistaken in his claim that [A] is “just anti-platonism with respect to God” for God (and other substances) exhibit the character they do in virtue of standing in the exemplification relation to the abstract properties they possess. Still, our parenthetical remark in [A] tips our hat: we are inclined to think the constituent approach is the way to go here. But, we need not limit ourselves to a constituent approach in avoiding the bootstrapping objection. Rather, we could (and perhaps should) have said the following: [A*] God’s essential platonic properties exist a se (i.e. they are neither created nor sustained by God, yet they are exemplified by the divine substance) [A*] highlights the fact that both the relational and constituent approach to property possession is open to the defender of MTA: Either God exemplifies platonic properties that exist extra se (on the relational approach) or that inhere within the divine substance (on the constituent approach).2 Further, on [B], to say that God is an Aristotelian substance is to endorse the claim that God is a final cause of all His parts. As a final cause, the divine substance explains why it possesses the essential properties that it does and why it possesses the essential properties it does as a deep unity. God is not the “efficient cause of Himself” (74n. 2) as Craig wonders, rather the whole—as a final cause—is logically prior to its parts and the fundamental ground of its parts—hence, God is ultimate in explanation. Welty suggests that God’s creating propositions such as (E) God exists simply relocates the bootstrapping worry. If propositions are divine thoughts brought about by the activity of thinking, and causing something to exist is to cause its essence to be exemplified, then in bringing about (E), God causes the property being true to be exemplified by (E), thereby causing His own existence. Formally stated, the argument seems to go as follows: (5) If God causes (E), then God causes the property being true to be exemplified by(E). (6) If God causes the property being true to be exemplified by (E), then God causes His own existence. (7) God causes (E). (8) Therefore, God causes His own existence. [ Page ] 77 The principle grounding (6) seems to be that “x makes true y” entails “x causes y” or (more accurately and awkwardly, since y is a proposition) “x causes the object y is about.” Far from it. Socrates’ drinking the hemlock makes it true that Xantippe is a widow, but it doesn’t follow that Socrates’ drinking the hemlock causes her to become a widow (Davidson 1999, 283). Hence, we reject (6), and thus avoid the incoherency charge in this iteration of the bootstrapping objection. On MTA, God is the creator of all propositions, and in the Biggest Bang (see Leftow 2012) God freely (and eternally) thinks up all possible creatures and possible states of affairs thereby fixing all necessary alethic truths and falsehoods. On this picture, it makes no sense to say that God thereby brings about His own existence! Yandell claims that the nontrivial truth of (9) If abstracta did not exist, then God would not exist entails that “God depends for God’s existence on there being the abstracta that God must create” (66). In our reply to his lead essay we respond to this worry in greater detail. Here let us say the following. On MTA, the nontrivial truth of (9) is grounded in the fact that God is the creator of all abstracta (setting aside His essential properties). While it is true that the absence of abstracta entails God’s absence, it is false that God thereby depends for His existence on abstracta. The existential dependence is the other way around given the causal asymmetry between God and abstracta. There is no otiose dependency in view, and no divine bootstrapping on MTA. Worries regarding divine conceptualism There are two substantial objections to MTA that remain. Both concern the concep- tualist understanding of propositions. A proposition, we say, is a truthbearer. Further, possessing truth entails being an intentional object: An object that is of or about something, that represents the world (or some part of it) as being thus and so. This is precisely what concrete sentence inscriptions and platonic3 abstracta cannot do— not in themselves anyway.4 Thoughts, by contrast, are indisputably and essentially intentional. They are, says the proponent of MTA, composite wholes: specific mental arrangements of (brutely) intentional parts—Locke’s “invisible ideas.” Of course if all we have at our explanatory disposal is human mental activity, the lifespan of a proposition will be fleeting indeed, lasting only as long as we happen to be thinking it, and existing in just those worlds where we do so. In short, there won’t be any necessary truths (/falsehoods). The best course is to recognize a supra-natural realm of divine cognitive activity. A Proposition (capital ‘P’) is a divine thought: an ordered arrangement of divine ideas. Propositions are abstract in the sense of being multiply instantiable in human minds; but they’re not mind-independent abstracta of the platonic variety. (Thus contra Craig and Yandell, there is no incoherence in saying that God is a concrete being whose thoughts are abstract.) It doesn’t follow though, as Shalkowski fears, that our thoughts are literally identical with God’s. Instantiation [ Page ] 78 doesn’t entail identity. Our thoughts, as we say, are mere approximations and partial graspings of those in God’s mind. Now on to the objections. The Composition Objection. It is “not obvious” (says Yandell) and “not clear” (says Welty) that propositions have parts—namely, concepts or ideas. This may be so. But then again we don’t so much as slyly suggest that our “parts proposal” has that irresistible and evident lustre Locke extolled. It’s not a deliverance of introspection; it’s an inference to the best explanation. That it lacks Lockean luminosity in no way counts against it. Unfortunately, Yandell and Welty claim that the “parts proposal” isn’t even a good explanation. Thus Welty comments: “This is part and parcel of Russells (failed) analysis of propositions” (67). But that’s not why Russell’s analysis failed: because it held that propositions have parts. It failed because it invoked the entirely wrong sort of parts—parts that were painfully nonintentional (e.g. Quine himself), and thus impotent to account for a proposition’s being about anything. Yandell’s concern lies elsewhere. We should reject the “parts proposal,” he tells us, because “propositions are primary” and concepts are merely .“propositional abilities that persons have.” This follows if we accept this claim: “that S has the concept of being a cow insofar as S knows what is true if and only if there are cows” (66). Here Yandell seems to say that you have the concept being a cow only if you know there are cows is a true proposition. But surely that is incorrect. Graham Oppy, we may assume, grasps or apprehends the concept of God. But it hardly follows that he knows there is a God. He’ll be the first one to tell you that! In general, to grasp the concept of being an F, you don’t have to know that there are any Fs. There is no threat to the “parts proposal” here. The Content Objection. Oppy isn't inclined to think that propositions are truth- bearers; nor are they to be identified with thoughts. Rather, on his favored view, there are tokens (e.g. the inscription “Quine is wise”), propositions (e.g. the content of “Quine is wise”), and tokenings (e.g. my producing the token “Quine is wise”). Oppy’s claim is that only tokenings are truthbearers, since only tokenings are intentional. There are two principal difficulties with this suggestion. First, tokenings aren’t truthbearers. A tokening—whether verbal, written, or thought—is an act or event. However, as C. S. Lewis so aptly put it, “events in general are not ‘about’ anything and cannot be true or false” (1947, 21). The slamming of a door, for instance, isn’t “about” anything. It’s the sort of thing that “happens” or “occurs.” But it’s nothing even remotely like an intentional object that could represent a state of affairs. Thus it couldn’t possibly be true or false. The same thing goes for tokenings. Secondly, why think that thoughts and propositions are distinct? On Oppy’s view, a thought tokening is the producing of a thought—a mental token. Suppose we agree. Now consider this token: (T) The thought that Quine is wise. The propositional content of (T) is presumably (P) Quine is wise. Oppy declares that (T) and (P) are distinct. This isn’t obvious. If propositions can exist in worlds where there are no human beings, and indeed no concreta at all (as the [ Page ] 79 proponent of MTA holds), then (P) won’t be a physical object. It will be something nonphysical: an abstract platonic object, perhaps, or an immaterial thought. Now (P) is about Quine and represents him as being wise; hence, it can’t be a platonic object. Like it or not, then, we must say that (P) is a thought. Which thought? Well, obviously, the thought that Quine is wise. But notice that’s just (T) itself. Contra Oppy, therefore, there really is no difference between (T) and (P). At any rate, thus sayeth the modified theistic activist. Notes 1 There are sophisticated defenses of bare particulars in Moreland and Pickavance (2003) and Sider (2006). For those who feel a little queasy, think of an individuator in Wolterstorff’s (1991, 543) way: a particular that just is a nature. 2 For more see Gould (2011a and 2013) and Moreland (2001 and 2013). 3 The astute reader will notice that we use “platonic” in a more technical sense when talking about intentionality. In one sense, as Gould makes clear in the Introduction (n. v), “platonism” is just the view that abstract objects necessarily exist. In this sense, we agree that propositions are in fact platonic. But, we deny that propositions are “platonic” in the sense that they exist in Plato’s heaven as brutely intentional entities. 4 Welty asks why platonists can’t “just infer that there are these intentional entities, and that is that” (67). The answer is that the inferences involved in indispensability arguments simply don’t deliver “intentional entities.” They give you—at best and if they work—only indefinite entities that play the role of truthbearers. Intentionality is “bestowed” after the fact. But simply to announce here that platonic abstracta are intentional is wholly gratuitous and unsupported. Not so, of course, for thoughts, whose intentionality is known by introspection, not indispensability. ***** This is the end of the e-text. This e-text was brought to you by Tyndale University, J. William Horsey Library - Tyndale Digital Collections *****